Resentment and Integration of Evil in Axiomatology




Resentment and Integration of Evil in Axiomatology

Submission to value hierarchies is sometimes associated with what Nietzsche called slave morality, which arises from resentment (Ressentiment)—a reactive stance where weakness reinterprets strength as evil. However, this association can be misleading. In many cases, the opposite holds true: authentic submission to well-structured value hierarchies belongs more to the realm of master morality, which affirms values actively rather than reactively.

In this article, we examine the distinction between slave and master morality in the context of the transference of evil, offering an Axiomatological view on how such transference can be recognized and reduced through internal alignment rather than projection or denial.


The Essence of Slave Mentality – Reactionary Lack of Potential


When it comes to slave morality, as described by Nietzsche, it stands outside the domain of master morality. It is not noble, strong, or affirmative—it emerges as a reactive posture from a place of weakness. Slave morality is the morality of those who have lost access to strength, vitality, and nobility. It is an involuntary condition of limitation, where the individual internally desires power or freedom but cannot realize it. This blocked will—the inherited and irreversible limitation of potential—is the ground from which Ressentiment grows. Slave morality is, in essence, a moral reinterpretation of weakness as virtue, not from choice but from necessity.

The individual governed by slave morality deems the traits of strength and mastery to be “evil” precisely because these traits are unattainable. Thus, the supposed moral high ground is not genuine—it is a compensatory response, masking impotence as moral superiority. What is condemned externally is, in most cases, what is secretly desired but unreachable.

It is often claimed that slave morality gives rise to Ressentiment, but Nietzsche more accurately presents the inverse: slave morality is a product of Ressentiment. It is a structure built to justify inner resentment, either in individuals or collective identities. This is the same psychological mechanism that underlies modern identity politics, where resentment precedes ideological formation. The group identity—and its slave-morality framework—is constructed as a justification for this prior resentment.

From the Axiomatological perspective, the core of slave mentality aligns with the absence of potential. The fewer the meaningful occasions (in terms of creative, moral, or existential possibility) accessible to an individual, the higher the probability of Ressentiment. This results in a reactive worldview, morally justified through slave morality but fundamentally driven by ontological stagnation—a life devoid of vertical alignment or constructive direction.


Connection to Axiomatology


The core of slave morality’s underlying resentment—Ressentiment—can be viewed, in Axiomatological terms, as a limitation of potential within a moment, echoing the constraints of presentational immediacy. However, it is more accurate to conceptualize this limitation through the lens of process theory: as a longer, causally interlinked chain of occasions whose overall potentiality—specifically as it relates to a given subject—has been systematically reduced over time.

This reduction is caused by an increasing number of limiting physical prehensions (e.g., inherited traits, environmental conditions, bodily constraints) as well as conceptual prehensions, many of which are shaped by accumulated repression, denial, and cognitive rigidity. When cognitive dissonance accompanies this structure—where the individual senses a gap between their current state and some imagined or desired potential—the dissonance itself deepens the loss of potential. Through the mechanism of causal efficacy, as described in Whiteheadian terms, each occasion carries forward the weight of prior stagnations, amplifying the disintegration of subjective coherence across time.


Exploring the Core Lack of Potential that Causes Resentment


A closer analysis of this decreasing potential reveals a dual structure:

  • Physical prehension–related limitations: biological givens, bodily restrictions, environmental constraints (e.g., social class, trauma), and the lingering effects of past occasions. These form the hard constraints of a subject’s lived actuality.

  • Conceptual prehension–related limitations: constrained semantic structures, empirical categories imposed by society, and internalized narratives. These include forms of self-deception, where imagination and memory reinforce denial and moral avoidance.

No matter how one attempts to rationalize or obscure the situation, the truth of limitation remains. The biological and psychological architecture of the individual often contains built-in fragilities that heighten the probability of Ressentiment. Twin studies and behavioral genetics research consistently show that trait dispositions—including susceptibility to chronic resentment, neuroticism, and low openness—are inherited to a substantial degree, estimated between 50–60%.

Furthermore, the personal past, through its network of related prehensions, also determines one's disposition toward resentment. In Axiomatological terms, when the value trajectory of past occasions constrains rather than enables the subject's upward alignment, the loss of potential becomes not just situational but structurally embedded—feeding the formation of slave morality and the moral justification of that very resentment.


Asymmetric Resentment – Slave and Master Morality Combined in One Individual


While Nietzsche often presents slave and master morality as distinct value systems held by different types of people, real-life moral psychology is far more complex. In everyday life, most individuals hold elements of both. It is common for someone to embody master morality in one domain of life while simultaneously adopting slave morality in another.

For example, a middle-aged man may feel strong and victorious in his career—confident, assertive, and self-determined—thus operating from a master-morality framework in his professional identity. At the same time, the same individual may harbor resentment and moralized avoidance in his personal life—particularly around family and relationships—especially if he perceives diminished options with age. In this domain, he might begin to deem the nuclear family model or romantic intimacy as "overrated" or "unnecessary," not from strength but from a reaction to loss—a typical move of slave morality, where what is unattainable is framed as immoral or undesirable.

Therefore, just as a person may affirm and create values in one area of life, they may also unconsciously react and negate values in another. This results in asymmetrical moral structure, where different parts of the self operate under opposing value logics. Without conscious selection and hierarchical ordering of values, morality becomes fragmented and inconsistent—dependent not on principle, but on circumstance and perceived control.



Propagation of Evil Through Resentment


“Evil” in the Axiomatological sense—referring to both the natural tragic components of life and moral evil arising from human actions—is not identical to Nietzsche’s use of “evil” within the framework of slave morality, where “evil” simply denotes what master morality deems good (e.g., strength, vitality, dominance). Nietzsche’s term is relational and polemical, not metaphysical.

Returning to evil in the Axiomatological sense, we observe a clear logic: natural evil often acts as a catalyst for moral evil. As established in Axiomatology, the nexuses of evil are almost always initiated by involuntary tragic events—death, illness, severe physical or psychological limitations—and then intensified by the moral failures of individuals, either through selfishness, cruelty, or disordered value hierarchies.

In many cases, this escalation occurs in moments where natural evil and latent moral weakness coincide, and the suffering from tragedy becomes co-opted or "weaponized" to justify resentment-driven actions. In such cases, resentment becomes the playground of evil—a space where false narratives of victimhood are used to rationalize destructive behavior. This is not meaningful suffering but performative or misdirected suffering, which conceals moral failure behind a mask of pain.

The key insight is this: embodying master morality in one area does not protect us from channeling resentment into destructive behavior in another. In fact, the lack of potential or meaning in one field often drives the individual to use achievements in another field to justify or conceal resentment.

Resentment always carries a justificatory logic. Thus, framing one’s strength in one life domain as a moral counterweight to unaddressed resentment in another is often a form of self-deception. Instead of creating a moral "balance," this division leads to compartmentalized disintegration of the self.

From the Axiomatological standpoint, the solution is not to justify resentment through strength elsewhere, but to direct conscious attention to the field where evil manifests, where resentment lives, and to restore potential through alignment with one’s higher moral order (SIVH and WOG). Only then can the individual stop the recursive propagation of evil and begin meaningful moral reconstruction.


Competing Fractional Slave Morality


It can even be argued that evil may more easily manifest when an individual demonstrates excellence and upholds the standards of master morality in certain areas of life—particularly when those actions are outwardly beneficial to others. This visible success can generate a sense of internal moral superiority, which then serves as an unconscious justification for moral failure or neglect in other areas.

 

The psychological mechanism behind this kind of fragmented moral self-assessment is rarely obvious to the person themselves. What results is a moral blind spot—a false belief that virtue in one domain offsets the consequences of resentment or passivity in another.

Hannah Arendt once observed:

“The sad truth is that most evil is done by people who never make up their minds to be good or evil.”

This statement reflects the danger of moral indecision—not overt malice, but passive moral incoherence. Steven Pinker further clarifies the psychological camouflage of everyday evil:

“If the myth of pure evil is that evil is committed with the intention of causing harm and an absence of moral considerations, then it applies to very few acts of so-called 'pure evil,' because most evildoers believe what they are doing is forgivable or justifiable.”


Thus, the real danger lies not in clear, deliberate malice but in justified passivity, where one’s apparent morality in one field conceals unconfronted resentment in another.

This brings us to the essential insight: master morality in one field does not prevent the spread of resentment in others. Without a well-structured Structured Internal Value Hierarchy (SIVH), the individual lacks the integrative framework needed to coordinate moral alignment across life domains. The result is fractional morality—virtuous in parts, but vulnerable elsewhere.

The real threat, then, is not simply the presence of resentment, but its undetected justification and principled escalation in areas that remain morally unstructured. Axiomatology insists that unless every field of life is oriented by a coherent SIVH, the probability of resentment-induced evil remains high—even, or especially, in those who are otherwise seen as successful or virtuous.


Failure to Integrate Evil as a Debt


In Axiomatology, the temptation to carry forward evil can be resisted through a structured three-part process: preparation, voluntary confrontation in a safe environment, and meaningful suffering in alignment with one’s Structured Internal Value Hierarchy (SIVH). However, in many cases, individuals fail to complete this process. Below we examine one of the core types of failure: the failure to suffer, which often results in direct punishment of others.


Failure to Suffer the Evil – Direct Punishment of Others


When confronted with evil—especially when its source is personal betrayal, injustice, or existential limitation—it is immensely difficult to suffer through it without developing resentment. Even when the confrontation occurs in a safe setting, the first instinct often is not to suffer, but to react. One of the most primal reactions is the externalization of suffering through punishment—a direct form of retaliation.

From both Nietzschean and Axiomatological perspectives, this drive toward punishment arises from a perceived violation of a moral-economic balance. Nietzsche argued that conscience, in its early form, was not moral but mnemonic—a system built through pain and memory to enforce promises and obligations. As he put it:

“To breed an animal with the right to make promises—is not this the paradoxical task that nature has set itself with regard to man?” (Genealogy of Morality, Second Essay)


In this early social contract logic, a moral transaction (a promise, a commitment, a duty) creates a debt. When this debt is violated, a response is demanded to restore balance—not through moral elevation, but through compensatory force. Nietzsche writes:

“Punishment developed as a form of compensation... its purpose was to engrave the law upon the memory of the offender.”


Thus, punishment functions psychologically as an economic act: a way to naturalize imbalance by settling the emotional account. In the Axiomatological context, this corresponds to a refusal to suffer the evil internally and instead project it outward through destructive action.


The Mechanics of "Paying the Debt"

In this mode of failure, the individual avoids suffering by transferring their inner conflict onto others. The one who becomes the object of punishment need not be the original source of pain—any available target may serve. This is not a processing of evil, but a propagation—a short-circuiting of suffering that bypasses moral integration.

This is the psychological mechanism behind many forms of drive-discharge behavior: punishment, cruelty, even verbal aggression that serves no restorative function but simply continues the cycle of evil. In Nietzschean terms, this is a form of Ressentiment—a reaction not rooted in strength but in impotence disguised as justice.

From the Axiomatological standpoint, this is a failure to suffer in both the existential and moral sense. It is a refusal to carry the weight of evil voluntarily, resulting in the continuation of its force through unintegrated action.

This scenario corresponds to the Odyssean failure to bind oneself to the mast—to willingly suffer the pull of temptation under restraint. Without the mast (the vertical anchor), one becomes a conduit for chaos, acting out pain instead of transforming it.


Blunt Suffering – Bad Conscience Neutralized Through the Image of God

The second failure to integrate evil occurs when the individual internalizes the instinct to pass evil on but does not transmute it. That is, the destructive drives cannot be externalized or acted upon; there is no sacrificial outlet to “pay” the psychological debt in the outside world. As a result, the individual is left with no option but to suffer through the pain inwardly.

This generates what both Nietzsche and Axiomatology recognize as bad conscience—a psychic condition produced by repression and suppression, where societal or internal limitations block the expression of drives. Nietzsche famously wrote:

“All instincts which do not discharge themselves outwardly turn inward—this is what I call the internalization of man: it marks the start of what is called the soul.”

Here, guilt is not a reflective moral awareness but a neurotic symptom of suppressed drives—a self-inflicted cruelty. Often, the individual decides to carry the burden (consciously or not), simply because they lack the potency, courage, or means to do otherwise. This results in suffering without active transformation—a kind of mute endurance.


The Mechanics of "Paying the Debt"


In this scenario, religion becomes the surrogate mechanism for settling the inner imbalance. In Christian theology, the logic of atonement is that God sacrifices Himself to Himself through the Son, thereby neutralizing humanity’s original sin. Nietzsche sharply critiqued this metaphysical inversion:

“God sacrifices himself for the guilt of mankind—God himself makes payment to himself... what a ghastly paradox.”

For Nietzsche, this is the culmination of slave morality: the debtor is forever guilty, and the creditor pays the price. Guilt, inherited through bloodlines, is compounded across generations, and the sacrifice of Christ merely extends the system—giving people a sense of being saved while keeping them eternally in debt.

This logic, Nietzsche argued, leads not to liberation but to the theological induction of guilt. It creates a framework in which the individual becomes integrated into a system that feeds on suffering. What seems redemptive is, at its core, parasitic.

Nietzsche called this the “spiritualization of cruelty,” seen clearly in the ascetic ideal:

“I suffer because I am guilty.”

In this system, suffering itself becomes proof of virtue. Practices like celibacy, fasting, self-denial, and martyrdom are valued not because they elevate, but because they internalize punishment. This is the will to nothingness—a moral structure where it is better to will suffering and emptiness than to confront the terror of meaninglessness.



The Axiomatological Critique


From the Axiomatological perspective, this kind of blunt suffering may align with the Will of God (WOG) on a cosmic or religious level, but it lacks internal moral integration. The suffering is a free-willed choice, but one that is oriented toward an externalized abstraction, not toward a value structure grounded in the individual’s own Structured Internal Value Hierarchy (SIVH).

In this case, there is no clear linkage between suffering and personal meaning. The suffering may temporarily prevent the external propagation of evil, but it does not produce self-regulated transformation. It contains evil, but it does not transmute it.

Compared to the Axiomatological model of Odysseus, who binds himself to the mast and navigates consciously through temptation, this model of suffering remains incomplete. It offers partial protection but does not lead to sustainable moral integration. In the long run, this path fails to offer a structure for enduring, meaningful transformation. It is palliative, not redemptive.


Meaningful Suffering – Personal Strength Through Transforming Instincts


When it comes to meaningful suffering, the underlying mechanics resemble those in the second scenario (blunt suffering), but with a crucial difference: the individual does not remain passive or bound to external abstractions. Unlike the suffering induced by bad conscience and institutional guilt, meaningful suffering in Axiomatology is voluntary, value-structured, and developmental.

Nietzsche, in the second essay of The Genealogy of Morals, offers a partial precedent. He viewed sublimation into culture, art, and philosophy as the most hopeful response to bad conscience. Rather than repress or sanctify instinctual drives, one can transform them into creative power. This transformation becomes a higher affirmation of life, not a denial of its darker impulses.

Nietzsche’s examples of sublimation include art, philosophy, heroic action, self-overcoming, laughter, irony, and Dionysian music.
He writes: “Man is an as-yet undetermined animal.”

This suggests that the task of human life is not to deny instinct but to own, shape, and elevate it. The tragic artist and the higher philosopher do not escape their suffering—they integrate it into a form that expresses and transcends it.

In Axiomatological terms, this process of sublimation becomes one part of a broader dynamic called meaningful suffering. It is not merely a redirection of energy, but a value-guided transformation. The individual does not just cope—they voluntarily suffer in alignment with their Structured Internal Value Hierarchy (SIVH).

This assumes a conscious structuring of values, where a hierarchy has been established and topped by a monotheistic value—a singular, absolute orientation point relevant to a given epoch of life. Without this top value, suffering cannot be directed upward; it remains chaotic or self-referential.

Thus, meaningful suffering becomes the path through which an individual can transmute pain into internal strength, fostering a new level of identity development. Suffering is no longer something merely to be endured or atoned for—it becomes a vehicle for growth, allowing the personality to evolve in fidelity to a structured moral order.

It is through this voluntary and value-aligned suffering that evil—whether internal or inherited—can be neutralized, absorbed, and redeemed, rather than propagated or repressed.


This article is free to read. For access to even more quality content, register now at no cost.

LOG IN OR REGISTER





Are you interested in collaborating with Everyoung Labs—whether on AI projects, sales channels, lead generation, corporate initiatives, or cutting-edge AI art? Just drop us a line, and let’s take your business—or your creative life—to the next level!